Flash Movie by Davin Heckman The Observing Body: Quantum Mechanics, the Anthropic Principles, and Panopticism [printable version]
C. Jason Smith
<1> When philosopher of history and science Michel Serres wrote of "that rare and narrow passage" between the human sciences and the exact sciences [1], he intended to suggest not only the infrequency and difficulty of such contact, but also the unwillingness on either side to engage in what could be a dangerous, low-profit venture. It seems a long haul back to our common origins in philosophia, and typically, efforts to regain common ground between the disciplines have approached the problem as a one-sided move from the exact sciences to the study of the humanities. Notable exceptions such as N. Katherine Hayles' Chaos Bound: Orderly Disorder in Contemporary Literature and Science (1990) do attempt to create the atmosphere of dialog; yet, while Hayles discusses how "Different disciplines are drawn to similar problems because the concerns underlying them are highly charged within a prevailing cultural context" [2] her text still operates largely as a science-based approach to the study of cultural texts. Those in the humanities may agree to the applicability of complex dynamics and field theory to the study of culture, but the inverse is not typically true. For example, while we find Hayles' application of scientific theory to culture "interesting" or even "enlightening," works such as Donna J. Haraway's Simians, Cyborgs and Women (1991) are deemed "intrusive" and are largely ignored by the scientific community. Practical applications of scientific theories to specific works in the humanities may be useful, but in essence, these projects either simply advocate or court the sciences and rarely seek common parallels in theory or practice which are mutually supporting and enlightening. We need to look again at what we have always had in common, at something which prefigures even philosophia: the means of observation.
<2> This study is grounded in two propositions: first, our bodies are the essential apparatus of all observation. (We may think of "body" in these terms as the "mind-body complex," but the mind-body dichotomy is not necessary to the argument.) Furthermore, based in our own sense of embodiment and observation of other bodies, our corporeality defines the starting point and ultimate limit of human perception. In essence, as Carl Gustav Jung writes in Archetypes and the Collective Unconscious (1959), "No one can escape from the prejudice of being human" [3]. In the humanities, Jung's sentiment has become a virtual given of any postmodern critical approach to the study of culture and its artifacts. In the sciences, however, the role of the observer in the observation and collection of data is somewhat of a sore spot as many scientists are feeling the necessity to assert in strong terms the essentially "human nature" of observation which seems to undermine the notion of scientific objectivity.
<3> Second, in scientific terms we are complex dynamical systems and this fact affects our observational capacity in a very real way. In the exact sciences, the critical problems of observation stem, at least in part, from the fields of quantum mechanics and of complex dynamical systems (more popularly Chaos Theory) where the objectivity of the human body as an observation "device"-via the eyes, nose, ears, mouth, brain, etc.-comes into question. As James Gleick writes in the often quoted Chaos: Making of a New Science (1987),
The paragon of a complex dynamical system and to many scientists, therefore, the touchstone of any approach to complexity is the human body. No object of study available to physicists offers such a cacophony of counterrhythmic motion on scales from macroscopic to microscopic: motion of muscles, of fluids of currents, of fibers of cells. No physical system has lent itself to such an obsessive brand of reductionism: every organ has its own micro-structure and its own chemistry, and student physiologists spend years just on the naming of the parts. Yet how ungraspable these parts can be! [4]
The body, in these terms, is a complex dynamical system, and from this position of complex embodiment we speak, we observe, and we produce knowledge. This fundamental fact ties all the disciplines together and supplies us with a common teleology, to maximize and improve observation.
Part One: Observing the Body
<4> It was the Enlightenment that consciously redefined the body as an apparatus of observation in order to observe, dominate, and eventually incorporate nature. In The Dialectic of Enlightenment (1972), Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno argue that the scientific impetus of the Enlightenment was not a liberating move in the quest for truth, but a quest for a power which ultimately enslaves. They indicate the Enlightenment motto "knowledge, which is power, knows no obstacles" [5] as a type of confession of the true goals of the Enlightenment. The emphasis on the power of the individual is directly related to the drive to dominate nature, a drive that inevitably turns back on itself and leads to the formation of individuals who are internally repressed. As Foucault writes in The Birth of the Clinic (1973), "What counts in the things said by men is not so much what they may have thought or the extent to which these things represent their thoughts, as that which systematizes them from the outset, thus making them thereafter endlessly accessible to new discourses and open to the task of transforming them" [6]. All observation becomes standardized so that Sournia may write in Logique et morale du diagnostic that "We 'observe' [a patient] in the same way that we observe the stars or a laboratory experiment" [7]. This relativization of the means of observation yields subjects whose function, in Horkeheimer and Adorno's terms, is to both add to the base of information as commodity or consume that commodity; subjects who are in Foucault's terms simultaneously reconstructed as both apparatus of observation (observer-bodies) and information production (subjects of the empirical gaze) where the whole relationship of signifier to signified is redistributed to the aims of observation [8]. As he writes in Discipline and Punish (1975),
The historical moment of the disciplines was the moment when an art of the human body was born, which was directed not only at the growth of its skills, nor at the intensification of its subjection, but at the formation of a relation that in the mechanism itself makes it more obedient as it becomes more useful, and conversely....Discipline increases the forces of the body (in economic terms of utility) and diminishes these same forces (in political terms or obedience) [9] .
Once subjects are redefined as apparatus of observation, observation itself necessarily reforms as a hierarchical structure as power is dissociated from the body and turned into an "aptitude" or "capacity." Discipline seeks to increase this capacity while at the same time changing the course of power so that while the subject becomes an ever more rigidly calibrated observation device the power associated with observation is bled away. In essence, the individual power associated with observation is reorganized towards the ends of observation in general.
<5> This reconstruction of subjects as apparatus for observation yields more or less rigidly calibrated -- educated and socialized -- subjects who may be categorized as "objective" to varying degrees within the observational system. Even the shoddiest of human observers could still supply data for the interpretation even if they could not supply the "correct" interpretation themselves. Freud's Dora, for example, comments upon her own life and dreams, but it is only through the clarifying observation of Freud that we believe Dora or understand her in any meaningful way. This hierarchization of observation necessitates a chain of command which in turn implies an Ultimate Observer or Final Observation. In analytical psychology, for example, that Ultimate Observer is Freud himself as he designed and taught his theory and analyzed his "disciples" before sending them out to analyze others. Of all the possible meanings of Dora's dream of a burning house and "a jewel case," Freud recontextualizes the information within his theory as "My 'jewel case' is in danger and if anything happens it will be father's fault" [10]. His higher-level observation effectively commits Dora's statement to a single context and a single reality where "jewel case" is symbolic of her vagina and the burning house the modus for her "loss" of it to Mr. K. The subject, then, can be imagined as caught in an infinite regress of observation all the way back to an inferred "Final Observer" who would be able to realize the fullness and meaning of the data. Of course, the fact that Dora ultimately rejected Freud's analysis reminds us that, at least on a local level, two realities can exist and hierarchical observation does not always have the intended effect on the observed.
<6> The problems of interaction between observer and observed are fairly easy to understand when we are dealing with individual humans, especially when we consider that Freud's interpretations are no longer generally considered accurate. We simply do not all see the same way and generally accepted interpretations change over time, which is the very reason the scientific method was adopted in the first place in order to counteract individual subjectivity. As suggested earlier, the real problem of observation arises in the hard sciences and specifically in quantum mechanics where problems of subjectivity, supposedly eliminated (or greatly reduced) by the scientific method, re-emerge at the base of all observation in the smallest, most essential form of matter in the universe.
<7> According to quantum mechanics, all reality is (to some degree) observer-dependant. "In general," Stephen Hawking writes in A Brief History of Time: From the Big Bang to Black Holes (1988), "quantum mechanics does not predict a single definite result for an observation. Instead, it predicts a number of different possible outcomes and tells us how likely each of these is" [11]. The difference in the possible outcomes is observer dependant and as John Gribbon explains in his In Search of Schrödinger's Cat (1984), all vision involves bouncing protons of light off objects and into our eyes. A photon doesn't disturb large objects like a passing semi-truck on the Interstate very much, so we don't expect the tuck to be affected by simply looking at it, though we may wish it was. By looking at the truck, we do change it, though the change infinitesimally small. Observation effects everything we observe and ourselves. An electron, however, is so small that we have to use electromagnetic energy with a short wave-length in order to "see" it at all. And as Gribbon explains, "Such gamma radiation is very energetic, and any photon of gamma radiation that bounces off an electron and can be detected by our experimental apparatus will drastically change the position and momentum of the electron -- of the electron is an atom, the very act of observing it...may knock it out of the atom altogether" effectively dismantling it [12]. At the particle level, the base for all other observation, observer and observed are intertwined and their paths forever changed by their interaction. Form this starting point in quantum mechanics emerged a theory which eventually had repercussions up the observational scale from the smallest particles to the universe.
<8> To understand the full implication of what one particle could change we turn to Erwin Schrödinger's metaphorical cat. As he explains in "Naturwiss,"
A cat is penned up in a steel chamber, along with the following diabolical device (which must be secured against direct interference by the cat): in a Geiger counter there is a tiny bit of radioactive substance, so small, that perhaps in the course of one hour one of the atoms decays, but also, with equal probability, perhaps none; if it happens, the counter tube discharges and through a relay releases a hammer which shatters a small flask of hydrocyanic acid. If one has left the entire system to itself for an hour, one would say the cat still lives if meanwhile no atom has decayed. The first atomic decay would have poisoned it. The Y [theta] function of the entire system would express this by having in it the living and the dead cat (pardon the expression) mixed or smeared out in equal parts [13].
The mathematical equation, for those interested, looks like the following where theta=1 over the square root of 2 (theta "dead" + theta "alive"):
Schrödinger's metaphor is constructed as a cat in a sealed box with a vial of poison gas attached to a proton detector. If all circumstances are favorable to the creation of a proton, what happens to the cat? Is it alive or dead? According to quantum theory, the proton will at the same time be created and strike the detector and not be created and not strike the detector, so that the answer to Schrödinger's question is a paradoxical "yes and no." Without an outside observer opening the box and committing to one reality or another, then, theorists argued that both events have happened: live cat, dead cat. The implication is, as James Gleick summarizes, "Gone was the luxury of supposing that a single reality existed, that the human mind had reasonably clear access to it, and that the scientists could explain it" [14].Most physicists agree that there are five ways to resolve the paradox: the first is solipsism, or to assume that the only thing verifiable is the self so the seeming paradox is just part of everything else outside the self which cannot be known. Physicist would reject this possibility out of hand as inconsistent with the goals and means of science.
<9> The second possibility, and generally considered the simplest, is that any being with consciousness can collapse the wave functions (the mathematical symbol of multiple cats) by observation, effectively either committing the universe to one reality or another or identifying which universe we already occupy. Practically, the paradox is a local event contained in the box itself. This possibility is called the Copenhagen interpretation and as Barrow and Tipler summarize,
According to quantum theory, it is necessary to include some physics of the observer or measuring apparatus in the analysis if one wishes to talk about the result of a measurement on a system. A moment's reflection will show that the essential feature of a measuring apparatus is the ability to record the result of a measurement. The essence of a successful measurement is the transfer of information about the system being measured to the memory of the apparatus [15].
Which is to say, the act of observing properly and "recording" (or remembering) the data resolves the paradox. However, there is a further implication: "In the opinion of Heisenberg and Weizsäcker, the Copenhagen Interpretation implies that properties of objects do not exist until they are observed; the properties are 'latent' but are not 'actual' before the observation" [16] or that "the act of observation is responsible for bringing properties of physical systems into existence [17].
<10> The third possibility is that a community of observers can collectively collapse wave-functions. One observer looks in the box which starts the process which is verified and solidified through the hierarchy of observation. Implicit in this interpretation is the effect of the observer on the system being observed.
<11> Fourth, there is some sort of Ultimate Observer who is responsible for the collapse of wave functions. In essence, the Final Observer is constructed as the un-observable, the last on the chain of observables who clarifies and solidifies all previous observation. The Christian Jahova would fit the bill nicely as omniscience is the essence of the Final Observer and the fact of omniscience, in this case, actually explains omnipotence. In The Physics of Immortality: Modern Cosmology, God and the Ressurection of the Dead (1994), Tipler terms this Ultimate Observer the "Omega Point" (essentially our own descendents in the a galactic computer) which comes into being in the far future and from that position collapses all wave functions.
<12> Fifth, Wave functions never collapse (as there is no ultimate observer). The best known interpretation of this possibility is "Everett's Friends Paradox." With no Ultimate Observation, all possibilities are, mathematically at least, possible. As John Gribbon explains,
Everett's interpretation [of Schrödinger's Cat] accepts the quantum equations entirely at face value and says that both cats are real. There is a live cat, and there is a dead cat; but they are located in different worlds. It is not that the radioactive atom inside the box either did or did not decay, but that it did both. Faced with this decision, the whole world -- the universe -- split into two versions of itself, identical in all respects except that in one version the atom decayed and the cat died, while in the other the atom did not decay and the cat lived [18].
The opening of the box is not the moment when the universe splits but only the moment of recognition of which universe the observer belongs. We might think of a series of observers going all the way back, but unlike the previous possibility, Everett suggests that as an observer is supplanted by another observer, he is observed and vice versa, therefore, for Everett's interpretation the Ultimate Observer is discounted as a mathematically logical possibility. The Ultimate Observer is simply a paradoxical answer to a paradox because how can an observer exist who is not observed (if she was observed she would not be the Ultimate Observer at all, and so on).
<13> The interpretations of Schrödinger's Cat applied not only to Quantum Mechanics, but to many of the other sciences as well because as Tipler writes, "everything in sight is a quantum system" [19].And that includes us humans as well.
Part Two: Observing the Universe
<14> Based on our role as quantum-system observers, Barrow and Tipler, among others, developed what has come to be called The Anthropic Cosmological Principle: a series of principles focused on the role of the observer in the Universe based on quantum mechanics and defined under one rubric.
<15> The basic fact of observation derived from Quantum Mechanics, according to Barrow and Tipler, is that "we are a carbon-based life-form which spontaneously evolved on an earth-like planet around a star of G-2 spectral type, and any observation we make is necessarily self-selected by this absolutely fundamental fact." Our bodies, in essence, are measuring devices "whose self-selection properties must be taken into account, just as astronomers must take into account the self-selection properties of optical telescopes" [20]. This selection effect suggests that data is limited by what can be observed; i.e. the smallest "quanta" is now a quark because we can't see anything smaller (yet). All of which implies that that we must always take into accounts the limits of the observation devices we use beginning with the device which is "us." In other words, what we have come to call "the subject" is an observation apparatus fine-tuned to observe the universe from the smallest quanta, to the mundane motes of dust, to the galactic rim. But, to what end? Well, as Robert Penn Warren's Jack Burden states in All the King's Men (1946), "The end of man is to know." Complete observation is both our telos (purpose) and thantos (end).
<16> The base premise of the Anthropic Cosmological Principle states that we cannot conceive of a universe without us because we would not be in that universe to conceive of it. The very term "without us" asserts that we are here and any conception can only be in comparison to our presence; the a priori of observation is the presence of an observer. As Barrow and Tipler explain, "The Anthropic Principles seek to link aspects of the global and local structure of the Universe to these conditions necessary for the existence of living observers" [21]. In essence,
the basic features of the Universe, including such properties as its shape, size, age and laws must be observed to be of a type that allows the evolution of observers, for if intelligent life did not evolve in an otherwise possible universe, it is obvious that no one would be asking the reason for the observed shape, size, age and so forth of the universe [22].
The Anthropic Cosmological Principle is broken down by Barrow and Tipler into three separate postulates: "The Weak Anthropic Principle" (or WAP), "The Strong Anthropic Principle" (SAP), and "The Final Anthropic Principle" (FAP).
<17> The Weak Anthropic Principle states that "The observed values of all physical and cosmological quantities are not equally probable but they take on values restricted by the requirement that there exist sites where carbon-based life can evolve, and by the requirement that the Universe be old enough for it to have already done so" [23]. Or, to restate, only on a planet where carbon-based life and intelligence evolves is it possible to wonder about the origin of carbon-based life in the Universe. Barrow and Tipler make the distinction of "carbon-based" life because other universes could conceivably evolve without "us" (carbon-based intelligence) with non-carbon-based intelligence, but these universes would not necessarily include us. In this view, intelligence is not a necessary, but a sufficient condition for the presence or creation of the Universe.
<18> The Strong Anthropic Principle posits that "The Universe must have those properties which allow life to develop within it at some stage in its history" [24]. This view supports several other possibilities. First, there exists one possible Universe "designed" with the goal of generating and sustaining observers, which suggests that the a priori of the Universe is mind. We could say that intelligence, wherever it might exist, is equivalent on the galactic scale to the frontal lobe in man and the other higher mammals. Even more, the sum total of all minds in the Universe is the frontal lobe of the Universe, or will be at some point in the future.
<19> Second, the SAP suggests that observers are necessary to bring the Universe into being (this premise is also called the Participatory Anthropic Principle, or PAP), which is basically an extension of the previous proposition with the exception that the Universe does not exist as such until it "knows itself" through the evolution of intelligence. There are some interesting lines of influence between this view and Marx's First Historical moment and we could say, in essence, that the Universe does not enter history until it evolves intelligence to interact with it through the work of observation. Finally, the SAP suggests that an ensemble of other, different universes are necessary for the existence of our Universe [25]. Which is to say that "all possible worlds" must exist in order for this universe to exist.
<20> The Final Anthropic Principle is stated as "Intelligent information-processing must come into existence in the Universe, and, once it comes into existence, it will never die out" [26]. The FAP suggests that "information processing" is central to the existence of the Universe, or as Timothy Leary jokes in his popular work on complex dynamics, Chaos and Cyberculture (1994), the "you-niverse" [27]. In this case, the evolution of intelligence is a necessary condition to the existence of the Universe, and is, in a word, the reason the Universe comes into existence at all.
<21> The Anthropic Principle, in each of its various forms, is a cosmic extension of Heisenberg's Uncertainty Principle and the theories behind Schrödinger's Cat Paradox, extensions which attempt "to restrict the structure of the Universe by asserting that intelligent life, or at least life in some form, in some way selects out the actual Universe from among the different imaginable universes: the only 'real' universes are those which can contain intelligent life, or at the very least contain some form of life" [28]. In sum, intelligent life exists in the Universe and must exist in order to "know" the Universe, or any part of it, which may be one of many possible universes (WAP), and/or by that observation to "realize" the Universe, which may be the only Universe or one of many, any one of which might be dependent upon observers (SAP). As long as intelligent information processing exists, the Universe will exist, and is, in effect its raison d' être (FAP).
<22> The Universe and intelligence (of which humans are at least a part) are inter-dependant in a complex system of interaction that is evolving from intelligence towards complete, complex observation. In the Anthropic Cosmological Principles, observation is the first tool which humans use to remake their universe, and by extension and feed-back, internalize the Universe. The rest of the discussion will support, to some extent, the Weak and Strong Anthropic Principles, but it is in the Final Anthropic Principle that we find the most use for critical positioning to the effect that the Universe cannot exist without the observer. And it is from the position that intelligence exists in order to observe that we return to Foucault and the Panopticon.
Conclusions
<23> In Discipline and Punish, Michel Foucault critiques Jeremy Bentham's now infamous Panopticon vision of the prison which is constructed with a central tower and surrounding cells. "In short," Foucault writes, "it reduces the principle of the dungeon; or rather of its three functions -- to enclose, to deprive of light and to hide -- it preserves only the first and eliminates the other two. Full lighting and the eye of a supervisor capture better than darkness....Visibility is a trap" [29]. The ultimate goal of the Panopticon is "to induce in the inmate a state of consciousness and permanent visibility that assures the automatic functioning of power.... [P]ower should be visible and unverifiable" [30]. In essence, "The Panopticon is a machine for dissociating the see/being seen dyad: in the peripheric ring, one is totally seen, without ever seeing; in the central tower, one sees everything without being seen" [31].
<24> Foucault's point, of course, is not just that the Panopticon existed in Bentham's vision and in practical application in prisons, but that the power structure it represents exists everywhere in our culture. We must remember that this spreading of the Panopticon was Bentham's ultimate goal and the prison is but a poor shadow of what he intended as the prison is too obviously one-side as the prisoners cannot enter the tower and see. In society at large, however, the Panopticon operates so that an observer may observe at a single glance, not only the subjects of observation, but also other observers as well. And the observer must always assume that he is also observed [32]. The Panopticon is the product of a long process of the internalization of observation within the subject with its progression from public tortures and executions to the physical movement of punishments from public to internal spaces. Foucault is clear that the process of internalization of observation is an ongoing one. On this point, Tipler and Foucault are in complete agreement as both would say that observation has become central and is increasing. Foucault would characterize this increase in observation as serving the needs of Power while Tipler would say the increase in observation is teleological and leads to the Omega Point and the survival of intelligence in the Universe. However, this is simply a matter of scale as on the human level observation reinforces power which leads to yet more observation ad infinitum, the logical outcome of which would be progressive expansion until the entire universe was continually under reciprocal observation at every point at all times. This outcome is not only analogous to the Omega Point, it is the Omega Point. But, is this what Foucault intended when he wrote Discipline and Punish?
<25> No matter Foucault's intention in Discipline and Punish, most critics read his critical retelling of the history of the prison as proscriptive rather than descriptive, or, at the very least, use his theory as such. This reaction is understandable as panopticism, at least in Occidental culture, is a continual source of fear and paranoia. We might think here of projective works such as George Orwell's 1984 (1948) which predict one ultimate outcome of such as process. Even more contemporary, popular works like Star Trek: The Next Generation and Voyager express the fear of panopticism as a major, recurring theme in the ever-popular Borg episodes [33]. This fear of panopticism has roots in Occidental mythology and finds its major expression in the Tower of Babel myth from the Old Testament where the greatest sin was, according to the word of Jehova, that the people should unite: "And the Lord said, Behold, the people is one, and they have all one language; and this they begin to do: and now nothing will be restrained from them, which they have imagined to do." As Serres interprets, "An ingenious, intelligent, organized, articulate, and sedulous people undertake to build. The Tower of Babel will reach the sky. Near the end, however, the project fails, so it is said, through a confusion of tongues. In the desert there will remain some stones, a whole gigantic ruin slowly split and slaked by waters and wind, mastic trees, frost" [34]. They would have been the people who, with the panoptical technology of the tower, could see unilaterally and universally. They would have been able to see the pattern of life passing below them, see their borders, any of them and all of them. The fulfillment of the Panopticon is what Jehovah tried to stop because Jehovah is already at the center of the Panopticon. Panopticism, true panopticism, undermines and displaces Jehovah (the "high tower" of Psalms) as all intelligence would be able to "see" unilaterally.
<26> Donna J. haraway's voicing of the "new myth" of the cyborg, in Simians, Cyborgs, and Women, is an important step in the direction of unilateral vision which begins in panopticism. As she writes, "Vision in this technological feast becomes unregulated gluttony; all perspective gives way to infinitely mobile vision, which no longer seems just mythically about the god-trick of seeing everything from nowhere, but to have put the myth into ordinary practice. And like the god-trick, this eye fucks the world to make techno-monsters....But of course that view of infinite vision is an illusion, a god-trick" [35]. And more:
We need to learn our bodies, endowed with primate color and stereoscopic vision, how to attach the objective to our theoretical and political scanners in order to name where we are and are not, in dimensions of mental and physical space we hardly know how to name. So, not so perversely, objectivity turns out to be about particular and specific embodiment, and definitely not about the false vision promising transcendence of all limits and responsibility. The moral is simple: only partial perspective promises objective vision [36].
Objectivity, then, has nothing to do with grand scale observation, as suggested by quantum mechanics and the Anthropic Cosmological Principle. The Panopticon, originally conceived in the tower and its extension, the observatory, is effectively an observatory internalized. C. G. Jung addresses just such an issue when he writes of Archetypes that "Endless repetition has engraved these experiences into our psychic constitution, not in the form of images filled with content, but at first only as forms without content, representing merely the possibility of a certain type of perception and action" (48). Foucault's rendering of the Panopticon is a contemporary archetypal representation which is internalized so that the subject carries with them an ever-present observation as the a priori of action. But, need this be a source of fear? There is no evidence that it was for Foucault, nor that he intended to suggest anything other than realization of the fact of observation as a critical necessity. In fact, we could say that if Foucault was advocating anything at all it would be self-awareness of the role of observation in the functioning of power. He is perfectly clear that observation is inescapable and the best we can hope for is slight modifications in the cycles of inscribing observation. If, as the Anthropic Cosmological Principle asserts, the purpose of intelligence is observation, then the telos, or end, of intelligence is optimum observation where intelligence serves the needs of observation and not inverse.
<27> By my reading Foucault's critical interpretation of the Panopticon and the Anthropic Cosmological principle are not only analogous, but mutually supporting. Foucault has hypothesized at the societal level what is already established (in theory) in physics at the quantum level and in Cosmology at the cosmic level. The three parts of the puzzle fit nicely together and it is a very short reach indeed to convert Foucault into physics and vice-versa. In both the Panopticon and the Anthropic Principles, the human is a transient phase observation apparatus which will be outmoded (probably in the far future) in the interests of the evolution of observation. If observation is the purpose of intelligence in the Universe, then anything which stands in the way of complete (unilateral and non-hierarchical) observation is questionable at best. Our end, our telos and transformation through death of the human subject, is to eliminate obstacles to observation. The Anthropic Principles already have a term for this unity of observation: the Omega Point.
<28> The Enlightenment redefined the body as an apparatus of critical observation stationed within an observational hierarchy which presumes a "final" observation or "theory of everything." Traditional science, however, rejects teleology as a prejudice of the observer in an attempt to "objectify" observation. This rejection of teleological hypotheses is one of the fundamental divisions between the hard sciences and human sciences as, by their very nature, the human sciences operate on teleological premises. The various forms of the Anthropic Cosmological Principle, however, rooted in quantum mechanics and complex dynamics consciously incorporate this teleological view inherent in the dynamics of observation and thereby reconnect themselves with the human sciences at the observational cornerstone of thought. The path of observation is the most fundamental and accessible route in the project of a mutually supporting theory between the disciplines. Primary to the goal of observation is the exploration of borders, boundaries and so-called "givens," and most importantly, anything constructed as "natural." This project is already underway, but needs a new impetus. The conflation of the panoptical theory of power with the Anthropic Cosmological Principle will serve as the theoretical bridge between the human sciences and the exact sciences. The technology of observation must be self-consciously incorporated and expanded. The observed must become the observer and vice-versa ad infinitum until hierarchy as such comes to mean as little as "0" without "1."
Notes
[1] Michel Serres, Hermes: Literature, Science, Philosophy, 18. [^]
[2] N. Katherine Hayles, Chaos Bound: Orderly Disorder in Contemporary Literature and Science, xi. [^]
[3] Carl Gustav Jung, The Archetypes and the Collective Unconscious, 63. [^]
[4] James Gleick, Chaos: Making of a New Science, 297. [^]
[5] Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno,The Dialectic of Enlightenment, 4. [^]
[6] Michel Foucault, The Birth of the Clinic: An Archeology of Medical Perception, xix. [^]
[7] qtd. in Foucault, Birth of the Clinic, xv. [^]
[8] Foucault, Birth of the Clinic, xix. [^]
[9] Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison, 138. [^]
[10] qtd. in Jerry M. Burger, Personality (Stamford, CT: Wadsworth, 2000) 63. [^]
[11] Stephen Hawking, A Brief History of Time: From the Big Bang to Black Holes, 55. [^]
[12] John Gribbon, In Search of Schrödinger's Cat: Quantum Physics and Reality, 156-57. [^]
[13] Qtd. in John Barrow and Frank Tipler, The Anthropic Cosmological Principle, 465. [^]
[14] Gleick, Chaos, 14. [^]
[15] Barrow and Tipler, The Anthropic Cosmological Principle, 472. [^]
[16] Ibid. 468-69. [^]
[17] Ibid. 463. [^]
[18] Gribbon, In Search of Shrödinger's Cat, 238. [^]
[19] Frank J. Tipler, The Physics of Immortality: Modern Cosmology, God and the Ressurection of the Dead, 31. [^]
[20] Barrow and Tipler, The Anthropic Cosmological Principle, 3. [^]
[21] Ibid. 13. [^]
[22] Ibid. 1-2. [^]
[23] Ibid. 16. [^]
[24] Ibid. 21. [^]
[25] Ibid. 22. [^]
[26] Ibid. 23. [^]
[27] Timothy Leary, Chaos and Cyberculture. [^]
[28] Barrow, The Physics of Immortality, 511. [^]
[29] Foucault, Discipline and Punish, 200. [^]
[30] Ibid. 201. [^]
[31] Ibid. 202. [^]
[32] Ibid. 207. [^]
[33] Editor's note: The interior of Borg vessels are traditionally shown to be cellular in nature, comprising a series of compartments which the Borg "citizens" are housed within -- as such, the Borg live in a perfect realization of Bentham's Panopticon, but the nature of their observation is decidedly more discrete than the system of observation engendered by the architecture of the ship. [^]
[34] Genesis 11:6. [^]
[35] Serres, Hermes, 123. [^]
[36] Donna J. Haraway, Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention of Nature, 189-90. [^]
[37] Ibid. 48. [^]
Works Cited
Barrow, John. and Frank Tippler. The Anthropic Cosmological Principle. New York: Oxford UP, 1986.
Foucault, Michel. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. 1975. Trans. Alan Sheridan. New York: Vintage, 1995.
----. The Birth of the Clinic: An Archeology of Medical Perception. 1973. Trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith. New York: Random, 1994.
Gleick, James. Chaos: Making of a New Science. New York: Penguin, 1987.
Gribbon, John. In Search of Schrödinger's Cat: Quantum Physics and Reality. New York: Bantam, 1984.
Haraway, Donna J. Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention of Nature. New York: Routledge, 1991.
Hawking, Stephen. A Brief History of Time: From the Big Bang to Black Holes. New York : Bantam Books, 1988.
Hayles, N. Katherine. Chaos Bound: Orderly Disorder in Contemporary Literature and Science. Ithaca: Cornell UP, 1990.
Horkheimer, Max and Theodor W. Adorno. The Dialectic of Enlightenment. 1972. Trans. John Cumming. New York: Seabury, 1982.
Jung, Carl Gustav. The Archetypes and the Collective Unconscious. 1959. Bollingon Series XX. Trans. C. F. Hull. Princeton: Princeton UP, 1969.
Leary, Timothy. Chaos and Cyberculture. Ed. Michael Horowitz. Berkeley: Ronin, 1994.
Orwell, George. 1984. 1948. New York : New American Library, 1983.
Scarry, Elaine. The Body in Pain: The Making and Unmaking of the World. New York: Oxford UP, 1985.
Serres, Michel. Hermes: Literature, Science, Philosophy. Ed. Josué V. Harari & David F. Bell. Baltimore : Johns Hopkins UP, 1982.
Tippler, Frank J. The Physics of Immortality: Modern Cosmology, God and the Ressurection of the Dead. New York: Random, 1994.
Warren, Robert Penn. All the King's Men. New York: Harcourt, 1946.